System F\(_\omega^{++}\)

\(F_\omega\) is the calculus of higher-kinded type constructors, combining two axes of the lambda cube (polymorphism and type operators).

The syntax of \(F_\omega\) is an extension of \(F\). First, we need to adjust our syntax to use type constructors (or just "constructors") instead of just types. By convention, we will use \(\tau\) to denote a nullary constructor, a constructor kinded at \(*\) (see below).

\[\require{bussproofs} c, \tau := \alpha \mid c \rightarrow c \mid \forall (\alpha : k).c \mid \lambda (\alpha : k) .c \mid c\ c \]

where \(\alpha\) is a type variable used in quantification and type abstraction.

Next, we will add \(k\), to denote kinds:

\[ k := * \mid k \rightarrow k \]

We also need terms to inhabit those types:

\[ e := x \mid \lambda (x:\tau).e \mid \Lambda(\alpha:k).e \mid e[\tau] \]

Our context, \(\Gamma\), may contain judgments about types and terms.

\[ \Gamma := \cdot \mid \Gamma, x:\tau \mid \Gamma : \alpha:k \]

You may also see the kinding judgment written as \(\alpha :: k\).

Finally, as noted earlier, we will need to extend \(F_\omega\) with primitive product kinds to handle ML modules (hence the ++ in \(F_\omega^{++}\)):

\[ \begin{aligned} k &:= \dots \mid k \times k \\ c &:= \dots \mid \langle c, c \rangle \mid \pi_1 c \mid \pi_2 c \end{aligned} \]

This language is defined statically as follows:

Rules 1.1 (Kinding): \(\Gamma \vdash c:k\)

\[ \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma(\alpha) = k$} \UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \alpha : k$} \end{prooftree} \qquad \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash c_1:*$} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash c_2:*$} \BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash c_1 \rightarrow c_2 : *$} \end{prooftree} \qquad \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma, \alpha:k \vdash c:*$} \UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \forall(\alpha:k).c:*$} \end{prooftree} \] \[ \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash c_1:k \rightarrow k'$} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash c_2:k$} \BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash c_1\ c_2 : k'$} \end{prooftree} \qquad \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma, \alpha:k \vdash c:k'$} \UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \lambda (\alpha:k).c : k \rightarrow k'$} \end{prooftree} \] \[ \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash c_1:k_1$} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash c_2:k_2$} \BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \langle c_1, c_2 \rangle : k_1 \times k_2$} \end{prooftree}\qquad \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash c:k_1 \times k_2$} \UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \pi_1 c : k_1$} \end{prooftree}\qquad \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash c:k_1 \times k_2$} \UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \pi_2 c : k_2$} \end{prooftree} \]

Rules 1.2 (Typing): \(\Gamma \vdash e:\tau\)

\[ \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma(x) = \tau$} \UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash x:\tau$} \end{prooftree}\qquad \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma, x:\tau \vdash e:\tau'$} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash \tau:*$} \BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \lambda(x:\tau).e : \tau \rightarrow \tau'$} \end{prooftree}\qquad \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma, \vdash e_1:\tau \rightarrow \tau'$} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash e_2:\tau$} \BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash e_1\ e_2 : \tau'$} \end{prooftree} \] \[ \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma, \alpha:k \vdash e:\tau$} \UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \Lambda(\alpha:k).e : \forall(\alpha:k).\tau$} \end{prooftree}\qquad \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash e:\forall(\alpha:k).\tau'$} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash \tau:k$} \BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash e[\tau] : [\tau/\alpha]\tau'$} \end{prooftree} \]

Note that these rules aren't sufficient -- If we have \(f : \forall(\beta:* \rightarrow *). \beta\ \texttt{int} \rightarrow \texttt{unit}\), we'd want to have \(f[\lambda(\alpha:*).\alpha]\ 12 : \texttt{unit}\). However, by the above rules, we type \(f[\lambda(\alpha:*):\alpha]\) at \(((\lambda \alpha.\alpha) \ \texttt{int}) \rightarrow \texttt{unit}\), not \(\texttt{int} \rightarrow \texttt{unit}\).

To remedy this, we need some way to express that \((\lambda \alpha.\alpha) \ \texttt{int}\) is equivalent to \(\texttt{int}\), which we will accomplish by defining a new judgment \(\Gamma \vdash c \equiv c' : k\), then adding to rules 1.2 the equivalence rule

\[ \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash e:\tau$} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash \tau \equiv \tau':*$} \BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash e:\tau'$} \end{prooftree} \]

Rules 1.3 (Constructor Equivalence): \(\Gamma \vdash c \equiv c':k\)

Equivalence \[ \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash c:k$} \UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash c \equiv c:k$} \end{prooftree} \qquad \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash c \equiv c':k$} \UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash c' \equiv c:k$} \qquad \end{prooftree} \qquad \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash c_1 \equiv c_2:k$} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash c_2 \equiv c_3:k$} \BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash c_1 \equiv c_3:k$} \end{prooftree} \]

Compatibility \[ \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash \tau_1 \equiv \tau_1' : *$} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash \tau_2 \equiv \tau_2' : *$} \BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \tau_1 \rightarrow \tau_2 \equiv \tau_1' \rightarrow \tau_2' : *$} \end{prooftree}\qquad \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma, \alpha:k \vdash \tau \equiv \tau' : *$} \UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \forall(\alpha:k).\tau \equiv \forall(\alpha:k).\tau':*$} \end{prooftree} \] \[ \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma, \alpha:k \vdash c \equiv c':k'$} \UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \lambda(\alpha:k).c \equiv \lambda(\alpha:k).c': k \rightarrow k'$} \end{prooftree} \qquad \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma, \alpha:k \vdash c_1 \equiv c_1':k \rightarrow k'$} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash c_2 \equiv c_2':k$} \BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash c_1\ c_2 \equiv c_1'\ c_2':k'$} \end{prooftree} \] \[ \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash c_1 \equiv c_1':k_1$} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash c_2 \equiv c_2':k_2$} \BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \langle c_1, c_2 \rangle \equiv \langle c_1', c_2' \rangle : k_1 \times k_2$} \end{prooftree} \] \[ \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash c \equiv c' : k_1 \times k_2$} \UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \pi_1c \equiv \pi_1c' : k_1$} \end{prooftree}\qquad \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash c \equiv c' : k_1 \times k_2$} \UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \pi_2c \equiv \pi_2c' : k_2$} \end{prooftree} \]

Reduction/beta \[ \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma, \alpha:k \vdash c:k'$} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash c':k$} \BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash (\lambda (\alpha:k).c)\ c' \equiv [c'/\alpha]c:k'$} \end{prooftree} \] \[ \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash c_1:k_1$} \UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \pi_1\langle c_1, c_2\rangle \equiv c_1:k_1$} \end{prooftree}\qquad \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash c_2:k_2$} \UnaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash \pi_2\langle c_1, c_2\rangle \equiv c_2:k_2$} \end{prooftree} \]

Extensionality/eta \[ \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash c:k_1 \rightarrow k_2$} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash c':k_1 \rightarrow k_2$} \AxiomC{$\Gamma, \alpha:k_1 \vdash c\ \alpha \equiv c'\ \alpha:k_2$} \TrinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash c \equiv c' : k_1 \rightarrow k_2$} \end{prooftree} \] \[ \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash \pi_1 c \equiv \pi_1 c':k_1$} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash \pi_2 c \equiv \pi_2 c':k_2$} \BinaryInfC{$\Gamma \vdash c \equiv c':k_1 \times k_2$} \end{prooftree} \]

Note that in many cases, we enforce that some constructors are types (kind \(*\)) -- we certainly can't have tuples or lambda abstractions underlying a \(\forall\) type, for example.

The first set of rules, labeled "equivalence", ensure that this is indeed an equivalence/congruence relation.

The beta rules are the interesting ones. With them, we can prove (assuming we've defined the relevant primitive types):

\[ \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{} \UnaryInfC{$\vdash \texttt{int}:*$} \AxiomC{} \UnaryInfC{$\beta:* \vdash \beta:*$} \BinaryInfC{$\vdash (\lambda \beta.\beta)\ \texttt{int} \equiv\texttt{int}:*$} \UnaryInfC{$\vdash (\lambda \beta.\beta)\ \texttt{int} \rightarrow \texttt{unit} \equiv \texttt{int} \rightarrow \texttt{unit}:*$} \end{prooftree} \]

Finally, the extensionality rules allow us to evaluate "underneath" tuples and lambda abstractions. You might think of these as conducting an "experiment" to see whether the relevant constructors behave equivalently.

Remarks

  • As it turns out, in this system, the \(:k\) annotation on equivalence is unnecessary, as they are uniquely determined by the kinding rules.

    Theorem (Regularity).

    1. If \(\vdash \Gamma\ ok\) and \(\Gamma \vdash e:\tau\), then \(\Gamma \vdash \tau:*\).

    2. If \(\vdash \Gamma\ ok\) and \(\Gamma \vdash c \equiv c':k\), then \(\Gamma \vdash c:k\) and \(\Gamma \vdash c':k\) Proof.

    3. By induction over the judgment \(\Gamma \vdash e:\tau\).

    4. By induction over the judgment \(\Gamma \vdash c \equiv c':k\). \(\square\)

    where \(\vdash \Gamma\ ok\) is a judgment ensuring that all types in \(\Gamma\) are well-formed.

    Rules 1.4 (Well-formed contexts): \(\vdash \Gamma\ ok\) \[ \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{} \UnaryInfC{$\vdash \cdot\ ok$} \end{prooftree}\qquad \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\Gamma\ ok$} \AxiomC{$\Gamma \vdash \tau:*$} \BinaryInfC{$\vdash \Gamma, x:\tau\ ok$} \end{prooftree}\qquad \begin{prooftree} \AxiomC{$\vdash \Gamma\ ok$} \UnaryInfC{$\vdash \Gamma, \alpha:k\ ok$} \end{prooftree} \]